Proof of Lemma: Every nonzero integer can be written as a product of primes












2












$begingroup$


I'm new to number theory. This might be kind of a silly question, so I'm sorry if it is.



I encountered the classic lemma about every nonzero integer being the product of primes in a textbook about number theory. In this textbook there is also a proof for it provided, and I'd like to understand why it is that the proof actually works.



The proof is as follows:




Assume, for contradiction, that there is an integer $N$ that cannot be written as a product of primes. Let $N$ be the smallest positive integer with this property. Since $N$ cannot itself be prime we must have $N = mn$, where $1 < m$, $n < N$. However, since $m$, $n$ are positive and smaller than $N$ they must each be a product of primes. But then so is $N = mn$. This is a contradiction.




I feel like this proof kind of presupposes the lemma. I think this line of reasoning could be strengthened using induction, and I've seen other proofs of this lemma that use induction. Can someone help me out? What am I missing and why do I think that this proof of the lemma is circular?










share|cite|improve this question









New contributor




Alena Gusakov is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.







$endgroup$








  • 2




    $begingroup$
    That argument is by induction. the result is easy to check for small numbers, so assume it holds up to $N-1$. Then $N$ is either prime, in which case we are done, or it factors as $atimes b$ with $1<a≤b<N-1$ and you can apply the inductive hypothesis to $a,b$. Same argument.
    $endgroup$
    – lulu
    2 hours ago






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    There is nothing missing in this proof. It is just fine. And why “two primes”?
    $endgroup$
    – José Carlos Santos
    2 hours ago










  • $begingroup$
    @JoséCarlosSantos Typo. Fixed.
    $endgroup$
    – Alena Gusakov
    2 hours ago










  • $begingroup$
    It's not circular, but it could be a lot clearer. It's not strictly necessary to say $n > 1$, since $m$ is positive and $mn$ is also positive.
    $endgroup$
    – Robert Soupe
    1 hour ago
















2












$begingroup$


I'm new to number theory. This might be kind of a silly question, so I'm sorry if it is.



I encountered the classic lemma about every nonzero integer being the product of primes in a textbook about number theory. In this textbook there is also a proof for it provided, and I'd like to understand why it is that the proof actually works.



The proof is as follows:




Assume, for contradiction, that there is an integer $N$ that cannot be written as a product of primes. Let $N$ be the smallest positive integer with this property. Since $N$ cannot itself be prime we must have $N = mn$, where $1 < m$, $n < N$. However, since $m$, $n$ are positive and smaller than $N$ they must each be a product of primes. But then so is $N = mn$. This is a contradiction.




I feel like this proof kind of presupposes the lemma. I think this line of reasoning could be strengthened using induction, and I've seen other proofs of this lemma that use induction. Can someone help me out? What am I missing and why do I think that this proof of the lemma is circular?










share|cite|improve this question









New contributor




Alena Gusakov is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.







$endgroup$








  • 2




    $begingroup$
    That argument is by induction. the result is easy to check for small numbers, so assume it holds up to $N-1$. Then $N$ is either prime, in which case we are done, or it factors as $atimes b$ with $1<a≤b<N-1$ and you can apply the inductive hypothesis to $a,b$. Same argument.
    $endgroup$
    – lulu
    2 hours ago






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    There is nothing missing in this proof. It is just fine. And why “two primes”?
    $endgroup$
    – José Carlos Santos
    2 hours ago










  • $begingroup$
    @JoséCarlosSantos Typo. Fixed.
    $endgroup$
    – Alena Gusakov
    2 hours ago










  • $begingroup$
    It's not circular, but it could be a lot clearer. It's not strictly necessary to say $n > 1$, since $m$ is positive and $mn$ is also positive.
    $endgroup$
    – Robert Soupe
    1 hour ago














2












2








2





$begingroup$


I'm new to number theory. This might be kind of a silly question, so I'm sorry if it is.



I encountered the classic lemma about every nonzero integer being the product of primes in a textbook about number theory. In this textbook there is also a proof for it provided, and I'd like to understand why it is that the proof actually works.



The proof is as follows:




Assume, for contradiction, that there is an integer $N$ that cannot be written as a product of primes. Let $N$ be the smallest positive integer with this property. Since $N$ cannot itself be prime we must have $N = mn$, where $1 < m$, $n < N$. However, since $m$, $n$ are positive and smaller than $N$ they must each be a product of primes. But then so is $N = mn$. This is a contradiction.




I feel like this proof kind of presupposes the lemma. I think this line of reasoning could be strengthened using induction, and I've seen other proofs of this lemma that use induction. Can someone help me out? What am I missing and why do I think that this proof of the lemma is circular?










share|cite|improve this question









New contributor




Alena Gusakov is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.







$endgroup$




I'm new to number theory. This might be kind of a silly question, so I'm sorry if it is.



I encountered the classic lemma about every nonzero integer being the product of primes in a textbook about number theory. In this textbook there is also a proof for it provided, and I'd like to understand why it is that the proof actually works.



The proof is as follows:




Assume, for contradiction, that there is an integer $N$ that cannot be written as a product of primes. Let $N$ be the smallest positive integer with this property. Since $N$ cannot itself be prime we must have $N = mn$, where $1 < m$, $n < N$. However, since $m$, $n$ are positive and smaller than $N$ they must each be a product of primes. But then so is $N = mn$. This is a contradiction.




I feel like this proof kind of presupposes the lemma. I think this line of reasoning could be strengthened using induction, and I've seen other proofs of this lemma that use induction. Can someone help me out? What am I missing and why do I think that this proof of the lemma is circular?







elementary-number-theory prime-numbers proof-explanation integers






share|cite|improve this question









New contributor




Alena Gusakov is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.











share|cite|improve this question









New contributor




Alena Gusakov is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.









share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited 1 hour ago









Robert Soupe

11.4k21950




11.4k21950






New contributor




Alena Gusakov is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.









asked 2 hours ago









Alena GusakovAlena Gusakov

112




112




New contributor




Alena Gusakov is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.





New contributor





Alena Gusakov is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.






Alena Gusakov is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.








  • 2




    $begingroup$
    That argument is by induction. the result is easy to check for small numbers, so assume it holds up to $N-1$. Then $N$ is either prime, in which case we are done, or it factors as $atimes b$ with $1<a≤b<N-1$ and you can apply the inductive hypothesis to $a,b$. Same argument.
    $endgroup$
    – lulu
    2 hours ago






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    There is nothing missing in this proof. It is just fine. And why “two primes”?
    $endgroup$
    – José Carlos Santos
    2 hours ago










  • $begingroup$
    @JoséCarlosSantos Typo. Fixed.
    $endgroup$
    – Alena Gusakov
    2 hours ago










  • $begingroup$
    It's not circular, but it could be a lot clearer. It's not strictly necessary to say $n > 1$, since $m$ is positive and $mn$ is also positive.
    $endgroup$
    – Robert Soupe
    1 hour ago














  • 2




    $begingroup$
    That argument is by induction. the result is easy to check for small numbers, so assume it holds up to $N-1$. Then $N$ is either prime, in which case we are done, or it factors as $atimes b$ with $1<a≤b<N-1$ and you can apply the inductive hypothesis to $a,b$. Same argument.
    $endgroup$
    – lulu
    2 hours ago






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    There is nothing missing in this proof. It is just fine. And why “two primes”?
    $endgroup$
    – José Carlos Santos
    2 hours ago










  • $begingroup$
    @JoséCarlosSantos Typo. Fixed.
    $endgroup$
    – Alena Gusakov
    2 hours ago










  • $begingroup$
    It's not circular, but it could be a lot clearer. It's not strictly necessary to say $n > 1$, since $m$ is positive and $mn$ is also positive.
    $endgroup$
    – Robert Soupe
    1 hour ago








2




2




$begingroup$
That argument is by induction. the result is easy to check for small numbers, so assume it holds up to $N-1$. Then $N$ is either prime, in which case we are done, or it factors as $atimes b$ with $1<a≤b<N-1$ and you can apply the inductive hypothesis to $a,b$. Same argument.
$endgroup$
– lulu
2 hours ago




$begingroup$
That argument is by induction. the result is easy to check for small numbers, so assume it holds up to $N-1$. Then $N$ is either prime, in which case we are done, or it factors as $atimes b$ with $1<a≤b<N-1$ and you can apply the inductive hypothesis to $a,b$. Same argument.
$endgroup$
– lulu
2 hours ago




1




1




$begingroup$
There is nothing missing in this proof. It is just fine. And why “two primes”?
$endgroup$
– José Carlos Santos
2 hours ago




$begingroup$
There is nothing missing in this proof. It is just fine. And why “two primes”?
$endgroup$
– José Carlos Santos
2 hours ago












$begingroup$
@JoséCarlosSantos Typo. Fixed.
$endgroup$
– Alena Gusakov
2 hours ago




$begingroup$
@JoséCarlosSantos Typo. Fixed.
$endgroup$
– Alena Gusakov
2 hours ago












$begingroup$
It's not circular, but it could be a lot clearer. It's not strictly necessary to say $n > 1$, since $m$ is positive and $mn$ is also positive.
$endgroup$
– Robert Soupe
1 hour ago




$begingroup$
It's not circular, but it could be a lot clearer. It's not strictly necessary to say $n > 1$, since $m$ is positive and $mn$ is also positive.
$endgroup$
– Robert Soupe
1 hour ago










3 Answers
3






active

oldest

votes


















2












$begingroup$

The proof is not circular, the key is in the second sentence: Let N be the smallest positive integer with this property.



We are allowed to say a least $N$ exists because of the well-ordering principle.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    I don't know if it's because of the well-ordering principle ... that's like using a hammer to slice through butter. One does not need the full strength of the AOC to prove such a simple statement.
    $endgroup$
    – Don Thousand
    2 hours ago










  • $begingroup$
    @Don What's AOC? I presume you're not talking about Alexandria Ocasio-Cortez.
    $endgroup$
    – Robert Soupe
    1 hour ago










  • $begingroup$
    @RobertSoupe: Axiom of choice. The more usual abbreviation is AC.
    $endgroup$
    – Nate Eldredge
    43 mins ago












  • $begingroup$
    @DonThousand: I think "well-ordering principle" here refers to the statement "the usual ordering on the natural numbers is a well order". The Axiom of Choice equivalent is "every set admits an ordering which is a well order" - that wouldn't really even help with this proof, since it would only tell us that there is some ordering of the natural numbers which is a well order - it doesn't tell us that the usual ordering is one.
    $endgroup$
    – Nate Eldredge
    41 mins ago



















2












$begingroup$

Although the proof by contradiction is correct, your feeling of unease is fine, because the direct proof by induction is so much clearer:




Take an integer $N$. If $N$ is prime, there is nothing to prove. Otherwise, we must have $N = mn$, where $1 < m, n < N$. By induction, since $m, n$ are smaller than $N$, they must each be a product of primes. Then so is $N = mn$. Done.







share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$





















    0












    $begingroup$

    A proof by induction has base case(s), Let m and n be said base cases. if it's true for m and true for n (not necessarily distinct), then because it's a product, it follows for mn. All the proof supposes, is N=mn for some base case ( primes or prime powers to start, in these cases) with m and n proved. Then it follows for N, which by saying N which
    originally was consider the least element of a set of counterexamples, has one, it eliminates all possible least elements for the set we originally supposed existed.






    share|cite









    $endgroup$













      Your Answer





      StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
      return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
      StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
      StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
      });
      });
      }, "mathjax-editing");

      StackExchange.ready(function() {
      var channelOptions = {
      tags: "".split(" "),
      id: "69"
      };
      initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

      StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
      // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
      if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
      StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
      createEditor();
      });
      }
      else {
      createEditor();
      }
      });

      function createEditor() {
      StackExchange.prepareEditor({
      heartbeatType: 'answer',
      autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
      convertImagesToLinks: true,
      noModals: true,
      showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
      reputationToPostImages: 10,
      bindNavPrevention: true,
      postfix: "",
      imageUploader: {
      brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
      contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
      allowUrls: true
      },
      noCode: true, onDemand: true,
      discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
      ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
      });


      }
      });






      Alena Gusakov is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.










      draft saved

      draft discarded


















      StackExchange.ready(
      function () {
      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3161147%2fproof-of-lemma-every-nonzero-integer-can-be-written-as-a-product-of-primes%23new-answer', 'question_page');
      }
      );

      Post as a guest















      Required, but never shown

























      3 Answers
      3






      active

      oldest

      votes








      3 Answers
      3






      active

      oldest

      votes









      active

      oldest

      votes






      active

      oldest

      votes









      2












      $begingroup$

      The proof is not circular, the key is in the second sentence: Let N be the smallest positive integer with this property.



      We are allowed to say a least $N$ exists because of the well-ordering principle.






      share|cite|improve this answer









      $endgroup$













      • $begingroup$
        I don't know if it's because of the well-ordering principle ... that's like using a hammer to slice through butter. One does not need the full strength of the AOC to prove such a simple statement.
        $endgroup$
        – Don Thousand
        2 hours ago










      • $begingroup$
        @Don What's AOC? I presume you're not talking about Alexandria Ocasio-Cortez.
        $endgroup$
        – Robert Soupe
        1 hour ago










      • $begingroup$
        @RobertSoupe: Axiom of choice. The more usual abbreviation is AC.
        $endgroup$
        – Nate Eldredge
        43 mins ago












      • $begingroup$
        @DonThousand: I think "well-ordering principle" here refers to the statement "the usual ordering on the natural numbers is a well order". The Axiom of Choice equivalent is "every set admits an ordering which is a well order" - that wouldn't really even help with this proof, since it would only tell us that there is some ordering of the natural numbers which is a well order - it doesn't tell us that the usual ordering is one.
        $endgroup$
        – Nate Eldredge
        41 mins ago
















      2












      $begingroup$

      The proof is not circular, the key is in the second sentence: Let N be the smallest positive integer with this property.



      We are allowed to say a least $N$ exists because of the well-ordering principle.






      share|cite|improve this answer









      $endgroup$













      • $begingroup$
        I don't know if it's because of the well-ordering principle ... that's like using a hammer to slice through butter. One does not need the full strength of the AOC to prove such a simple statement.
        $endgroup$
        – Don Thousand
        2 hours ago










      • $begingroup$
        @Don What's AOC? I presume you're not talking about Alexandria Ocasio-Cortez.
        $endgroup$
        – Robert Soupe
        1 hour ago










      • $begingroup$
        @RobertSoupe: Axiom of choice. The more usual abbreviation is AC.
        $endgroup$
        – Nate Eldredge
        43 mins ago












      • $begingroup$
        @DonThousand: I think "well-ordering principle" here refers to the statement "the usual ordering on the natural numbers is a well order". The Axiom of Choice equivalent is "every set admits an ordering which is a well order" - that wouldn't really even help with this proof, since it would only tell us that there is some ordering of the natural numbers which is a well order - it doesn't tell us that the usual ordering is one.
        $endgroup$
        – Nate Eldredge
        41 mins ago














      2












      2








      2





      $begingroup$

      The proof is not circular, the key is in the second sentence: Let N be the smallest positive integer with this property.



      We are allowed to say a least $N$ exists because of the well-ordering principle.






      share|cite|improve this answer









      $endgroup$



      The proof is not circular, the key is in the second sentence: Let N be the smallest positive integer with this property.



      We are allowed to say a least $N$ exists because of the well-ordering principle.







      share|cite|improve this answer












      share|cite|improve this answer



      share|cite|improve this answer










      answered 2 hours ago









      Edgar Jaramillo RodriguezEdgar Jaramillo Rodriguez

      1065




      1065












      • $begingroup$
        I don't know if it's because of the well-ordering principle ... that's like using a hammer to slice through butter. One does not need the full strength of the AOC to prove such a simple statement.
        $endgroup$
        – Don Thousand
        2 hours ago










      • $begingroup$
        @Don What's AOC? I presume you're not talking about Alexandria Ocasio-Cortez.
        $endgroup$
        – Robert Soupe
        1 hour ago










      • $begingroup$
        @RobertSoupe: Axiom of choice. The more usual abbreviation is AC.
        $endgroup$
        – Nate Eldredge
        43 mins ago












      • $begingroup$
        @DonThousand: I think "well-ordering principle" here refers to the statement "the usual ordering on the natural numbers is a well order". The Axiom of Choice equivalent is "every set admits an ordering which is a well order" - that wouldn't really even help with this proof, since it would only tell us that there is some ordering of the natural numbers which is a well order - it doesn't tell us that the usual ordering is one.
        $endgroup$
        – Nate Eldredge
        41 mins ago


















      • $begingroup$
        I don't know if it's because of the well-ordering principle ... that's like using a hammer to slice through butter. One does not need the full strength of the AOC to prove such a simple statement.
        $endgroup$
        – Don Thousand
        2 hours ago










      • $begingroup$
        @Don What's AOC? I presume you're not talking about Alexandria Ocasio-Cortez.
        $endgroup$
        – Robert Soupe
        1 hour ago










      • $begingroup$
        @RobertSoupe: Axiom of choice. The more usual abbreviation is AC.
        $endgroup$
        – Nate Eldredge
        43 mins ago












      • $begingroup$
        @DonThousand: I think "well-ordering principle" here refers to the statement "the usual ordering on the natural numbers is a well order". The Axiom of Choice equivalent is "every set admits an ordering which is a well order" - that wouldn't really even help with this proof, since it would only tell us that there is some ordering of the natural numbers which is a well order - it doesn't tell us that the usual ordering is one.
        $endgroup$
        – Nate Eldredge
        41 mins ago
















      $begingroup$
      I don't know if it's because of the well-ordering principle ... that's like using a hammer to slice through butter. One does not need the full strength of the AOC to prove such a simple statement.
      $endgroup$
      – Don Thousand
      2 hours ago




      $begingroup$
      I don't know if it's because of the well-ordering principle ... that's like using a hammer to slice through butter. One does not need the full strength of the AOC to prove such a simple statement.
      $endgroup$
      – Don Thousand
      2 hours ago












      $begingroup$
      @Don What's AOC? I presume you're not talking about Alexandria Ocasio-Cortez.
      $endgroup$
      – Robert Soupe
      1 hour ago




      $begingroup$
      @Don What's AOC? I presume you're not talking about Alexandria Ocasio-Cortez.
      $endgroup$
      – Robert Soupe
      1 hour ago












      $begingroup$
      @RobertSoupe: Axiom of choice. The more usual abbreviation is AC.
      $endgroup$
      – Nate Eldredge
      43 mins ago






      $begingroup$
      @RobertSoupe: Axiom of choice. The more usual abbreviation is AC.
      $endgroup$
      – Nate Eldredge
      43 mins ago














      $begingroup$
      @DonThousand: I think "well-ordering principle" here refers to the statement "the usual ordering on the natural numbers is a well order". The Axiom of Choice equivalent is "every set admits an ordering which is a well order" - that wouldn't really even help with this proof, since it would only tell us that there is some ordering of the natural numbers which is a well order - it doesn't tell us that the usual ordering is one.
      $endgroup$
      – Nate Eldredge
      41 mins ago




      $begingroup$
      @DonThousand: I think "well-ordering principle" here refers to the statement "the usual ordering on the natural numbers is a well order". The Axiom of Choice equivalent is "every set admits an ordering which is a well order" - that wouldn't really even help with this proof, since it would only tell us that there is some ordering of the natural numbers which is a well order - it doesn't tell us that the usual ordering is one.
      $endgroup$
      – Nate Eldredge
      41 mins ago











      2












      $begingroup$

      Although the proof by contradiction is correct, your feeling of unease is fine, because the direct proof by induction is so much clearer:




      Take an integer $N$. If $N$ is prime, there is nothing to prove. Otherwise, we must have $N = mn$, where $1 < m, n < N$. By induction, since $m, n$ are smaller than $N$, they must each be a product of primes. Then so is $N = mn$. Done.







      share|cite|improve this answer









      $endgroup$


















        2












        $begingroup$

        Although the proof by contradiction is correct, your feeling of unease is fine, because the direct proof by induction is so much clearer:




        Take an integer $N$. If $N$ is prime, there is nothing to prove. Otherwise, we must have $N = mn$, where $1 < m, n < N$. By induction, since $m, n$ are smaller than $N$, they must each be a product of primes. Then so is $N = mn$. Done.







        share|cite|improve this answer









        $endgroup$
















          2












          2








          2





          $begingroup$

          Although the proof by contradiction is correct, your feeling of unease is fine, because the direct proof by induction is so much clearer:




          Take an integer $N$. If $N$ is prime, there is nothing to prove. Otherwise, we must have $N = mn$, where $1 < m, n < N$. By induction, since $m, n$ are smaller than $N$, they must each be a product of primes. Then so is $N = mn$. Done.







          share|cite|improve this answer









          $endgroup$



          Although the proof by contradiction is correct, your feeling of unease is fine, because the direct proof by induction is so much clearer:




          Take an integer $N$. If $N$ is prime, there is nothing to prove. Otherwise, we must have $N = mn$, where $1 < m, n < N$. By induction, since $m, n$ are smaller than $N$, they must each be a product of primes. Then so is $N = mn$. Done.








          share|cite|improve this answer












          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer










          answered 2 hours ago









          lhflhf

          166k11172402




          166k11172402























              0












              $begingroup$

              A proof by induction has base case(s), Let m and n be said base cases. if it's true for m and true for n (not necessarily distinct), then because it's a product, it follows for mn. All the proof supposes, is N=mn for some base case ( primes or prime powers to start, in these cases) with m and n proved. Then it follows for N, which by saying N which
              originally was consider the least element of a set of counterexamples, has one, it eliminates all possible least elements for the set we originally supposed existed.






              share|cite









              $endgroup$


















                0












                $begingroup$

                A proof by induction has base case(s), Let m and n be said base cases. if it's true for m and true for n (not necessarily distinct), then because it's a product, it follows for mn. All the proof supposes, is N=mn for some base case ( primes or prime powers to start, in these cases) with m and n proved. Then it follows for N, which by saying N which
                originally was consider the least element of a set of counterexamples, has one, it eliminates all possible least elements for the set we originally supposed existed.






                share|cite









                $endgroup$
















                  0












                  0








                  0





                  $begingroup$

                  A proof by induction has base case(s), Let m and n be said base cases. if it's true for m and true for n (not necessarily distinct), then because it's a product, it follows for mn. All the proof supposes, is N=mn for some base case ( primes or prime powers to start, in these cases) with m and n proved. Then it follows for N, which by saying N which
                  originally was consider the least element of a set of counterexamples, has one, it eliminates all possible least elements for the set we originally supposed existed.






                  share|cite









                  $endgroup$



                  A proof by induction has base case(s), Let m and n be said base cases. if it's true for m and true for n (not necessarily distinct), then because it's a product, it follows for mn. All the proof supposes, is N=mn for some base case ( primes or prime powers to start, in these cases) with m and n proved. Then it follows for N, which by saying N which
                  originally was consider the least element of a set of counterexamples, has one, it eliminates all possible least elements for the set we originally supposed existed.







                  share|cite












                  share|cite



                  share|cite










                  answered 3 mins ago









                  Roddy MacPheeRoddy MacPhee

                  537118




                  537118






















                      Alena Gusakov is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.










                      draft saved

                      draft discarded


















                      Alena Gusakov is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.













                      Alena Gusakov is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.












                      Alena Gusakov is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.
















                      Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


                      • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

                      But avoid



                      • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

                      • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


                      Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


                      To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




                      draft saved


                      draft discarded














                      StackExchange.ready(
                      function () {
                      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3161147%2fproof-of-lemma-every-nonzero-integer-can-be-written-as-a-product-of-primes%23new-answer', 'question_page');
                      }
                      );

                      Post as a guest















                      Required, but never shown





















































                      Required, but never shown














                      Required, but never shown












                      Required, but never shown







                      Required, but never shown

































                      Required, but never shown














                      Required, but never shown












                      Required, but never shown







                      Required, but never shown







                      Popular posts from this blog

                      What other Star Trek series did the main TNG cast show up in?

                      Berlina muro

                      Berlina aerponto